Category: General

Welcome, David Icke fans!

Hi. You may very well be this blogpost because you’ve just heard the interview with David Icke that my friend Josh and I posted over at Podbean. If you have no idea what I’m talking about, go listen to said interview here.

Right, well, here’s a couple of links to inform new readers of who I am!

The Philosophy of Conspiracy Theories, a book I wrote on the topic of how we should take talk of conspiracy theories seriously.

(You might also like to look at the basis of that book, my PhD on conspiracy theories, free to view here.)

Other, more recent philosophical work can be found here at Academia.edu and ResearchGate.

Finally, this is possibly the greatest thing I have even gotten to do on TV (thus far):

On asking for name suppression when being principally opposed to it

So, Cam Slater plead guilty to soliciting the hack on The Standard (even though he’s now saying he didn’t solicit the hack; he was defrauded by Ben Rachinger, who claimed to have already hacked The Standard, and was offering Slater content on the proviso Slater hand over some money). Not just that, but Slater then sought permanent name suppression, despite having a long history of opposing name suppression in principle.

So, that’s interesting, but not exactly exciting.

I’ve held off writing anything on this update to the whole Ben Rachinger affair for two reasons.

  1. We haven’t learnt much which is new. Oh, we have confirmation now from Slater that he was involved (which is much better than the anguished sniping from both he and Rachinger all over the internet about it), but that part of the story was never really in doubt.
  2. The story is still ongoing. Slater plead guilty and got diversion (itself an interesting result given his previous convictions), but Rachinger is still going to have his day in court, in order to prove – among other things – that he was a police asset.

So, whilst we have Slater admitting some level of guilt here, the actual story of conspiracy which is the most interesting – the Rachinger tale – continues to bubble along. Rachinger continues to lash out and attack people like Rangi Kemara, Nicky Hager, and the like as being people variously involved in #dirtypolitics themselves, having let him down, et cetera. He also continues to maintain he knows who Rawshark is, and could out him at any moment. Then again, he’s made bold promises like this before, and never actually delivered upon them. It seems that few people take his claims seriously, but when they do – like Slater – the results are hardly pretty.

This all sounds negative and glum. Still, you would likely feel the same if you had spend days reading self-serving posts by Cameron Slater on how he is the real victim in this #dirtypolitics ordeal. His posts really are quite good, in that he’s successfully navigated the tricky waters of telling his commentators and audience he did a bad thing, but that the real enemies are the liberals and progressives out there who seek to cause him harm. It really is an astounding bubble that he and his followers live in.

Still, there are a few unanswered questions which come out of reading Slater’s ‘own’ ((Given we know people write for Slater’s blog under other names, who knows if he is actually wrote said content.)) commentary on the matter:

  1. Where did Lauda Finem get the incriminating photos of a phone showing salacious images from? Slater keeps saying ‘Ask them!’, yet surely he must be interested to know how pictures of his phone were ‘shopped’ to another site.
  2. Who was the mysterious funder Slater referred to? Did they actually exist?
  3. Is it true that the chat logs between Rachinger and Slater have been redacted at the request of the Crown?

The first question speaks to the strange relationship between Lauda Finem and Whale Oil blogs. Both site proprietors claim to have nothing to do with one another. People who have got to grips with the material claim otherwise, usually with quite compelling evidence. So, why maintain the fiction that there is no real connection between the two?

The other two questions are interesting just for the sheer fact that there is so much potential disinformation being bandied about by both Slater and Rachinger; its hard to take their individual claims about the other seriously, let alone their claims about themselves. Both Slater and Rachinger seem to have supported each other’s fantasies; Slater, for example, wanted proof of a plot to get him to commit suicide, whilst Rachinger wanted to be a player or powerbroker. It’s hard to know, when information is being traded in barbed blogposts or tweets what to make of certain extraordinary claims, claims which point towards sometimes complementary, sometimes contrary, allegations of conspiracy.

Will there be more to this? Well, I guess we have to wait and see what happens when Ben Rachinger goes to court, in order to prove that the State has conspired against him. I’m not ruling out the possibility Rachinger was used by the Police, but let’s just say that if that turns out to be the case, it’ll be interesting if their story and Ben’s end up being perfectly aligned.

An open letter to the hosts of Axons and Axioms on the irrationality of belief in conspiracy theories

Back when I was in Finland earlier this year, I listened to an episode of the podcast ‘Axons and Axioms’, a series which describes itself as ‘A podcast dedicated to all things philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience.’ Said episode was on conspiracy theories, and I really wasn’t very impressed by it. If the hosts honestly think they are dedicated to all things philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience, then they should have at least looked at the philosophical work on belief in conspiracy theories, rather than just mocked such beliefs outright. I wrote them a letter, which was never responded to. As such, I post it here as a warning to the curious.

Dear Tim and Derek.

My name is Matthew R. X. Dentith, an epistemologist who writes on conspiracy theories. I was just listening to your podcast on that same topic, and I thought I would drop you a line to offer some feedback.

Firstly, I was curious as to why you didn’t mention any of the philosophical literature on belief in conspiracy theories; since 1995 there has been a resurgence of interest in the topic, starting with Charles Pigden’s “Popper revisited, or what is wrong with conspiracy theories” (Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 25(1), 1995) through to my book, “The Philosophy of Conspiracy Theories” (Palgrave Macmillan, 2014). Over the past twenty years such philosophers as Brian L. Keeley, Lee Basham, David Coady, Juha Räikkä, Jason Taylor, Joel Bunting, Pete Mandik, Steve Clarke and the like have written on epistemic issues of belief in conspiracy theories, and I found it interesting that you didn’t present any of this research when declaring your case for a general scepticism of these things we call “conspiracy theories”. If you had, you might have found that many of the philosophers who write on this topic reject the idea belief in conspiracy theories is prima facie irrational, and argue instead that we need to appraise such theories on their merits. We cannot merely dismiss them just because they are called “conspiracy theories”.

As such, I would invite you to look at the topic again, but this time approaching it with respect to the philosophical literature. I have appended a somewhat comprehensive bibliography of recent work to this email.

Secondly, I was also curious as to why you didn’t talk about the large amount of social psychology lit on the topic either. Whilst it is much more sceptical of the warrant of conspiracy theories, it defends a much more nuanced case for a general scepticism than the one you presented.

Sorry if this email comes across as harsh, but I do think academics have a responsibility to present the current thinking of the day, and I think you dropped the ball in this case. A podcast devoted to the intersection of philosophy and psychology should not ignore work in either fields, let alone both (especially when a simple search in the Philosopher’s Index would have given you a lot of interesting material to play with).

Yours sincerely,

Matthew R. X. Dentith, PhD (Auckland)

Bibliography

  • Basham, Lee. 2011. ‘Conspiracy theory and rationality.’ In Beyond rationality, edited by Carl Jensen and Rom Harré, 49–87. Newcastle on Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
  • Basham, Lee, and Matthew R. X. Dentith. 2015. ‘Bad thinkers? Don’t be so gullible!’ 3 Quarks Daily, edited by S. Abbas Raza. http://www.3quarksdaily.com/3quarksdaily/2015/08/bad-thinkers-dont-be-so-gullible.html.
  • Buenting, Joel, and Jason Taylor. 2010. ‘Conspiracy theories and fortuitous data.’ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 40 (4): 567–78.
  • Cassam, Quassim. 2015. ‘Bad thinkers.’ Aeon, edited by Brigid Hains. March. http://aeon.co/magazine/philosophy/intellectual-character-of-conspiracy-theorists/.
  • Clarke, Steve. 2002. ‘Conspiracy theories and conspiracy theorizing.’ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (2): 131–50.
    • ———. 2006. ‘Appealing to the fundamental attribution error: was it all a big mistake?’ In Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate, edited by David Coady, 129-132. Hampshire, England: Ashgate.
    • ———. 2007. ‘Conspiracy theories and the internet – controlled demolition and arrested development.’ Episteme 4 (2): 167–80.
  • Coady, David. 2006. ‘Conspiracy theories and official stories.’ In Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate, edited by David Coady, 115-128. Hampshire, England: Ashgate.
    • ———. 2007. ‘Are conspiracy theorists irrational?’ Episteme 4 (2): 193-204
    • ———. 2012. What to believe now : applying epistemology to contemporary issues. Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Dentith, Matthew R. X. 2014. The philosophy of conspiracy theories. Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Feldman, Susan. 2011. ‘Counterfact conspiracy theories.’ International Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (1): 15–24.
  • Keeley, Brian L. 1999. ‘Of conspiracy theories.’ The Journal of Philosophy 96 (3): 109–26.
  • Levy, Neil. 2007. ‘Radically socialized knowledge and conspiracy theories.’ Episteme 4 (2): 181–92.
  • Lipton, Peter. 2004. Inference to the best explanation. Second Edition. London: Routledge.
  • Mandik, Peter. 2007. ‘Shit happens.’ Episteme 4 (2): 205–18.
  • Pigden, Charles. 1995. ‘Popper revisited, or what is wrong with conspiracy theories?’ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (1): p.3–34.
    • ———. Forthcoming. ‘Conspiracy theories and the conventional wisdom revisited’ In Secrets and Conspiracies, edited by Loukola, Olli. Rodopi.
  • Popper, Karl Raimond. 1969. The open society and its enemies. 5th ed. Vol. 2. London; Henley: Routledge Kegan Paul.
    • ———. 1972. Conjectures and refutations. Fourth Edition. Routledge; Kegan Paul.
  • Räikkä, Juha. 2009a. The ethics of conspiracy theorizing, Journal of Value Enquiry, 43, 457-468.
    • ———. 2009b. On political conspiracy theories, Journal of Political Philosophy, 17 (2), 185-201
  • Räikkä, Juha and Basham, Lee. Forthcoming. ‘Conspiracy theory phobia’. In Conspiracy theories and the people who believe them, edited by Joe Uscinski.

On the shoulders of giants

There is – as there is for everyone – a special circle of Hell for academics. The Peer Review Circle (as I believe Dante wittingly called it) is a place where everyone you say is questioned, and nothing you claim is accepted. It is a place where even the most reasonable suggestion is taken to be contentious, and arguments occur over the content of a simple gesture, like saying ‘Good morning’ to a friend. Yet this circle pales in comparison to the other academic Hell, the Hall of Unheard Voices. This is the place where certain academics – who have written on some niche or specialist subject – find themselves, howling into the darkness, their words ignored or unseen.

I recently found myself in this particular hell, joined by a number of my colleagues. The occasion was the publication of ‘Vice Epistemology’, a piece by the University of Warwick’s Quassim Cassam. Long-time readers of this blog will immediately recall that name, given discussion of his work in earlier posts (here and here) Cassam’s new piece – an extension of his ‘Bad thinkers’ article over at Aeon Magazine – is a curious beast. It purportedly tells the story of a conspiracy theorist by the name of Oliver, who only believes some particular 9/11 conspiracy theory due to being gullible, from which Cassam derives the claim all conspiracy theorists are wracked with epistemic vices. It is an article which seemingly explains why we are suspicious of conspiracy theories and conspiracy theorist, and is a welcome contribution to the debate. It’s just also one which is deeply weird.

Scan through Cassam’s article and you will note a curious lack. There is no reference whatsoever to any philosophical work on belief in conspiracy theories. For the uninitiated, here is a non-exhaustive list of recent work on that very topic:

  • Basham, Lee. 2011. ‘Conspiracy theory and rationality.’ In Beyond rationality, edited by Carl Jensen and Rom Harré, 49–87. Newcastle on Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
  • Basham, Lee, and Matthew R. X. Dentith. 2015. ‘Bad thinkers? Don’t be so gullible!’ 3 Quarks Daily, edited by S. Abbas Raza. http://www.3quarksdaily.com/3quarksdaily/2015/08/bad-thinkers-dont-be-so-gullible.html.
  • Buenting, Joel, and Jason Taylor. 2010. ‘Conspiracy theories and fortuitous data.’ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 40 (4): 567–78.
  • Clarke, Steve. 2002. ‘Conspiracy theories and conspiracy theorizing.’ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (2): 131–50.
    • ———. 2006. ‘Appealing to the fundamental attribution error: was it all a big mistake?’ In Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate, edited by David Coady, 129-132. Hampshire, England: Ashgate.
    • ———. 2007. ‘Conspiracy theories and the internet – controlled demolition and arrested development.’ Episteme 4 (2): 167–80.
  • Coady, David. 2006. ‘Conspiracy theories and official stories.’ In Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate, edited by David Coady, 115-128. Hampshire, England: Ashgate.
    • ———. 2007. ‘Are conspiracy theorists irrational?’ Episteme 4 (2): 193-204
    • ———. 2012. What to believe now : applying epistemology to contemporary issues. Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Dentith, Matthew R. X. 2014. The philosophy of conspiracy theories. Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Feldman, Susan. 2011. ‘Counterfact conspiracy theories.’ International Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (1): 15–24.
  • Keeley, Brian L. 1999. ‘Of conspiracy theories.’ The Journal of Philosophy 96 (3): 109–26.
  • Levy, Neil. 2007. ‘Radically socialized knowledge and conspiracy theories.’ Episteme 4 (2): 181–92.
  • Lipton, Peter. 2004. Inference to the best explanation. Second Edition. London: Routledge.
  • Mandik, Peter. 2007. ‘Shit happens.’ Episteme 4 (2): 205–18.
  • Pigden, Charles. 1995. ‘Popper revisited, or what is wrong with conspiracy theories?’ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (1): p.3–34.
    • ———. Forthcoming. ‘Conspiracy theories and the conventional wisdom revisited’ In Secrets and Conspiracies, edited by Loukola, Olli. Rodopi.
  • Popper, Karl Raimond. 1969. The open society and its enemies. 5th ed. Vol. 2. London; Henley: Routledge Kegan Paul.
    • ———. 1972. Conjectures and refutations. Fourth Edition. Routledge; Kegan Paul.
  • Räikkä, Juha. 2009a. The ethics of conspiracy theorizing, Journal of Value Enquiry, 43, 457-468.
    • ———. 2009b. On political conspiracy theories, Journal of Political Philosophy, 17 (2), 185-201
  • Räikkä, Juha and Basham, Lee. Forthcoming. ‘Conspiracy theory phobia’. In Conspiracy theories and the people who believe them, edited by Joe Uscinski.

How long would it take to read all of that? I wager little more than a week. Yet not one of those articles (or the many more that do not appear on that list) appear in ‘Vice Epistemology’. It’s almost as if Cassam was completely unaware that there existed an extant literature on the topic of belief in conspiracy theories within Philosophy.

That caveat is important, because Cassam does quote work on belief in conspiracy theories from outside the philosophical domain (some of which references the above works…); he has done some of his homework, just not all of it.

Maybe I’m old-fashioned, but when writing on a topic, I do like to cast about and see if anyone else has done any work in the area. It seems both prudent (who wants to be told ‘But x already said that!’) and polite (no one likes someone barging into their area of expertise, claiming to have reinvented their wheel). Cassam’s well-written article reads as imprudent and impolite; he reinvents a wheel that others have already discussed and discarded (it turns out it was the wrong colour; the hairdressers were right after all…). Cassam’s argument would be all the more stronger had he at least mentioned prior work only to dismiss it, but the lack of references comes across as ignoring a literature that would prove irksome to his thesis. ((Cassam knows of the work of other philosophers in the field; at least one colleague of mine has been in contact with him.))

Lest you think this is me simply complaining that I didn’t get cited on an article, let me say that, yes, I am annoyed by the lack of citation, but I’m also mollified by the fact none of my colleagues in Philosophy were either. Being left out when everyone else is invited is one thing; when no one you know makes the cut, then it’s hard to take it that personally. Rather, I’m astounded both by the fact Cassam did not think to make even a cursory reference to the larger philosophical literature (especially since some of it directly talks to his thesis of belief in conspiracy theories being due to character flaws on the part of conspiracy theorists), and that the editor and reviewers at ‘The Monist’ did not think to ask ‘Has anyone else written on this?’

Answers on a postcard. Meanwhile, tomorrow, another example of the above.

Podcast – When inferring to what Matthew thinks is the best

Modelling my reasoning – an update on conspiracism

So, that paper I’ve been working on, about conspiracist ideation? It’s hit version three, and in its latest incarnation I’ve made what might appear – at first – to be a major shift in my point-of-view.

Let me backtrack. In previous editions of this series I’ve discussed how to define conspiracism (the view that there is a kind of belief in conspiracy theories which is due to or caused by factors other than there being good arguments or evidence in favour of such theories), who counts as a ‘conspiracist’ (potentially everyone), and why we should stop claiming that we can use the views of some conspiracy theorists to judge the merit of conspiracy theories generally (don’t hate on the game just because you hate the playa). I’ve been shopping the paper around, and some of the feedback I’ve got has been incredibly useful.

One piece of criticism I’ve got from a colleague-who-also-happens-to-be-a-good-friend has perplexed me, though. Said friend and I saw a lot of views about the academic debate surrounding belief in conspiracy theories, and I thought we were on the same page when it came to this topic. Yet their feedback consistently indicated that we weren’t, and yet as far as I could tell, the problems they were describing in my paper seemed to get my view upside down. After a long email correspondence, I realised that the impression of conspiracism I gave in the paper didn’t exactly fit with what I was saying in response. That, in turn, made me realise my views about conspiracism and conspiracists had moved on from what I had written in the book. Not just that, but the paper was a hybrid of the old and the new, and the bits of the old were disguising the newness of the new!

In The Philosophy of Conspiracy Theories I argue that we should use the term ‘conspiracist’ to refer to wacky and weird conspiracy theorists. I endorsed a version of the perjorative gloss on conspiracy theorist because, well, it’s hard to get past the fact some conspiracy theorists are, for lack of a better term, wacky, and their beliefs are not predicated on good reasoning. When it came to writing up these thoughts some three years later, however, I motivated talk of conspiracist-style analyses with reference to recent literature by social scientists (who, as a class, typically treat belief in conspiracy theories as irrational). In the paper I argue that conspiracism is something social scientists diagnose as a feature of being a conspiracy theorist. This was a shift in position; I took it that when I was discussing conspiracism I was discussing something social scientists hold to as being true of the general class of conspiracy theorists. I contrasted that position with the claim that, at best, conspiracism is true only of some conspiracy theorists.

Obviously elements of my original position (let’s respect the common, pejorative usage of conspiracy theorising/conspiracy theorist) crept into the new paper. Time after time, email after email, my friend (and peer) kept talking about how I was defending what was, in essence, some claim about a personal propensity to believe conspiracy theories erroneously. I kept responding that I thought I was simply arguing that this is what many social scientists believe, and how I was stressing how we should not necessarily accept their diagnosis in this matter.

Looking back over the paper, I realise it was not particularly clear that my position had changed post the book. There I somewhat endorsed the terms ‘conspiracist’ and ‘conspiracism’, because I still thought it useful to keep some aspect of the pejorative gloss in use. In the new piece it was clear my analysis of what the social scientists were saying was accurate. But my own position? It was too opaque to at least one philosopher, and that was one philosopher too much.

So, what is my new view on this thing I call ‘conspiracism’? Well, whilst I am oft tempted to use the term ‘conspiracist’ to refer to weird conspiracy theorists (and have even encouraged others to do likewise), I guess I’m only using that now as a rhetorical ploy. Yes, I’m still prone to using ‘conspiracist’ to refer to conspiracy theorists whose views I think haven’t got an epistemic leg to stand on, but… Well, I should just drop it as a label, and critique the theory (rather than attack the theorist). When it comes to the academic notion of conspiracism… Well, it’s a thesis I take is evident in much social science critique of belief in conspiracy theories, and it is the belief that some conspiracy theorists hold to their conspiracy theories for factors other than arguments and evidence. My worry about conspiracist-styled critiques is they assume conspiracy theorists are generally conspiracists, and thus we can derive the belief that conspiracy theories are generally irrational. That I take it is a gross mischaracterisation; whilst all conspiracists will turn out to be conspiracy theorists, not all conspiracy theorists are conspiracists. We should not smear the beliefs of a general class (the conspiracy theorists) with the predilections of a (quite possibily hypothetical) few. That’s the real problem.